The Humanist Tradition read this

THE HUMANIST TRADITION( sourse of website)
45
Hobbe’s interpretation of Materialism was unusual in that he
made it the basis for political conservatism and suggested
that God was
corporeal
. This latter idea, paradoxical as it
may seem, stems from the logical position, likewise held by
some of the early Church Fathers, that there can be no such
thing as an incorporeal substance and that God, if he exists,
must have a body. Hobbes was also an iconoclast in under-
taking criticism of the Bible on documentary grounds. It is
no wonder that the Church of England looked upon him as a
doubtful ally, some of the more intolerant bishops wishing to
have him burned as a heretic. And it is more than possible
that Hobbes, who in his best-known book,
The Leviathan
,
attacked even Aristotle for compromising with religion be-
cause of “fearing the fate of Socrates,” at times wrote about
God and other religious topics with his tongue in his cheek.
The most significant resurgence of Materialism, however,
took pl
ace in France during the sec
ond half of the eighteenth
century as part of the great Enlightenment that stirred to its
depths the Western world. The French Encyclopedists, such
as La Mettrie and Helvetius, Holbach and Diderot, were able
to utilize the materialist philosophy as a powerful weapon
against religious superstition and the r
eactionary Catholic
Church. In his
System of Nature
Baron d’Holbach summed
up the materialist attitude toward religious supernaturalism:
“If we go back to the beginning of things, we shall always
find that ignorance and fear created the gods; that imagina-
tion, rapture, and deception embe
llished or distorted them;
that weakness worships them; that credulity nourishes them;
that custom spares them; and that tyranny favors them in or-
der to profit from the blindness of men.”
12
And the uncom-
promising Diderot exclaimed: “Men will never be free until
the last king is strangled in the entrails of the last priest!”
13
These French materialists, however, maintained the mecha-
nistic fallacies I have already mentioned and in addition ex-
46
THE PHILOSOPHY OF HUMANISM
tended them to their social theory.
During the nineteenth century leadership in the materialist
movement passed to Germany and to such men as Jacob
Moleschott and Ernst Haeckel, Ludwig Buchner and Ludwig
Feuerbach, Karl Marx and Frederick Engels. Haeckel was
the first important German biologist who wholeheartedly ac-
cepted the Darwinian doctrine of organic evolution. He used
that theory as the cornerstone of his popular philosophic
work,
The Riddle of the Universe
, wherein he showed con-
clusively that the mind as well as the body of humans had
evolved from animal species.
The brilliant Feuerbach, a much underrated figure in most
histories of philosophy, broke with orthodoxy early in his ca-
reer and lost his teaching post after it was discovered that he
was the author of an anonymous treatise attacking the idea of
personal immortality. In his most significant book,
The Es-
sence of Christianity
, Feuerbach demonstrated that the my-
thologies of traditional religion have their source in unful-
filled human feelings, longings, and needs. Human beings
deify their inward nature by projecting it outward as the idea
of God; “God is the highest subjectivity of man abstracted
from himself.”
14
The essential predicates of Divinity, such
as personality and love, are simply the human qualities we
value most highly. Although Feuerbach is ordinarily classi-
fied as a materialist, he himself at one time considered Hu-
manism as the most appropriate name for his philosophy.
Feuerbach had a profound influence on the philosophic
development of Marx and Engels. It was he, as Engels
states, who “in many respects forms an intermediate link
between Hegelian philosophy and our own conception.”
15
The Dialectical Materialism of Marx and Engels corrected
the mechanistic errors of the earlier materialist tradition and
gave full recognition to the dynamic, ever-changing character
of existence and to the infinite interrelatedness of phenomena
THE HUMANIST TRADITION
47
in both Nature and society. While Dialectical Materialism
considers that human thought is a function of the bodily or-
ganism, it believes that the mind is no mere passive reflector
of the outside world, but that it possesses a fundamental ini-
tiative and creativity, a power of working upon and remold-
ing the environment through the force of new ideas.
At the same time the Marxist materialists have carried on
and developed the intransigent antireligious doctrines of the
materialists who preceded them. Today there can be
little
question that Dialectical Materialism, while having its own
shortcomings, is the most influential variety of Materialism,
both because of its consistency and inclusiveness and also
because it is the official philos
ophy of Communist govern-
ments and parties throughout the world.
There are other philosophies of the past which, while not
specifically within either the naturalist or materialist cate-
gory, give strong support to the Humanist position. For ex-
ample, Auguste Comte, French thinker of the middle nine-
teenth century, made a stimulating if somewhat erratic ap-
proach to a consistent Humanism. Taking the facts and
methods of science as his starting point, Comte worked out a
far-reaching system, which he called
Positivism
. He used the
word
positive
, not as the opposite of
negative
, but as mean-
ing scientifically certain or assured.
During his late forties Comte reacted against his earlier
intellectualism following a deep emotional crisis associated
with his passionate, though Platonic, love for a beautiful and
intelligent woman, Clotilde de Vaux, and her untimely death
at thirty-one after he had known her for only a year. Comte
mourned at her tomb once a week and invoked her memory
in prayer three times a day. He referred to her as his angel of
inspiration and as a second Beatrice. Finally, he formally en-
sconced her in his system as a virtual saint and as the per-
sonification of the Ideal Female symbolizing the Great Being
48
THE PHILOSOPHY OF HUMANISM
(humanity).
All this accompanied Comte’s unfortunate transformation
of Positivism into a complex Religion of Humanity, replete
with rituals, sacraments, priests, and temples. For the wor-
ship of God he substituted the worship of humankind and for
the calendar of Christian saints a select list of the heroes of
human progress. Positivism, patterning its liturgy closely af-
ter that of the Roman Catholic Church, assumed some of the
objectionable features of a religious cult, and was soon
dubbed “Catholicism minus Christianity.” It was, moreover,
a cult overpersonalized in the image of its egotistic founder,
who in effect became the high priest of the new religion and
whose statue was prominently displayed in all the Positivist
temples.
Comte had a considerable vogue throughout the Western
world, but his thought took deeper root in Latin America
than in the United States. His followers have been particu-
larly active in Brazil, where in 1881 they established a Posi-
tivist Church. Its headquarters in Rio de Janeiro still func-
tions on a regular basis. Comte’s lasting influence on Brazil
is seen in the fact that inscribed on the national flag is his
maxim, “Order and Progress.” This is the only national em-
blem in the world that perpetuates the words of a philoso-
pher.
In England the versatile John Stuart Mill developed and
included in his philosophy of Utilitarianism the more scien-
tific aspects of Comte’s work, shunning its religious and
mystical elements. Mill’s writings also served as an invalu-
able stimulus to the democratic ideals that mean so much to
Humanism. His essay
On Liberty
ranks with Milton’s
Are-
opagitica
as one of the classic statements on freedom of
thought and the rights of the individual. “If all mankind mi-
nus one were of one opinion,” declared Mill, “and only one
person were of the contrary opinion, mankind would be no
THE HUMANIST TRADITION
49
more justified in silencing that one person, than he, if he had
the power, would be justified in silencing mankind....All si-
lencing of discussion is an assumption of infallibility.”
16
Positivism also inspired Herbert Spencer, systematic and
system-building British philosopher who outlined a general
theory of evolution several years before Darwin issued
The
Origin of Species
and who continued, after that notable
event, to apply the evolutionary hypothesis to every sector of
human history and thought. Spencer promoted his interpreta-
tion of evolution with such zeal that he overreached and dis-
credited himself. For he advocated a hard-boiled theory, sup-
posedly based on the Darwinian principle of the survival of
the fittest, that in society the economically su
ccessful, the
biologically fit, and the morally good are roughly equivalent.
In regard to supernaturalism, Spencer was an agnostic, that
is, one who believes there is not sufficient evidence either to
prove or disprove the existence of God and immortality. The
originator of the useful word
agnostic
was Thomas H. Hux-
ley, noted English biologist and popularizer of the Darwinian
theory. Since agnostics are doubtful about the supernatural,
they tend to be Humanists in practice.
Although it is difficult to classify Bertrand Russell, the
leading English philosopher of the twentieth century and a
member of the House of Lords, he properly belongs, I think,
in the tradition of naturalistic Humanism. This is attested by
the fact that he was president of the leading British Rational-
ist organization and a member of the Advisory Council of the
British Humanist Association. Lord Russell’s system is not
free of contradictions and has never shaken off entirely the
taint of subjectivistic theories of knowledge. Yet there is no
trace of supernaturalism in his conclusions; and he stands
thoroughly committed to the methods of democracy and sci-
ence. Russell’s most original contribution to philosophy lies
in his demonstration of the essential identity of logic and
50
THE PHILOSOPHY OF HUMANISM
pure mathematics. Early in his career he became a
militant
social reformer. On account of his pacifist views during the
First World War, Cambridge University dismissed him, and
the British Government imprisoned him for six months.
In 1940 political and
ecclesiastical pressures resulted in
Russell’s losing his appointment as professor of philosophy
at the College of the City of New York. A censorious faction
led by Episcopal Bishop William T. Manning had demanded
that Russell be ousted on the grounds that his books were
“lecherous, salacious, libidinous, lustful, venereous, eroto-
maniac, aphrodisiac, atheistic, irreverent, narrow-minded,
untruthful and bereft of moral fibre.”
17
Although CCNY it-
self stood firm for
academic freedom in the Russell case, the
higher city authorities overruled the College.
After the Second World War and despite his advanced
years, Russell took active leadership in the British and
world-wide movements for the ending of nuclear bomb test-
ing, for total disarmament in nuclear weapons, and for the
abolition of international war. Participating at the age of
ninety in a big peace demonstration in L
ondon in 1962, he
was arrested and sent to jail for a week.
Another distinguished thinker not easy to label is George
Santayana, who has likewise made signal contributions to
Humanism. Born in Spain, he came to maturity in the United
States and taught philosophy for many years at Harvard Uni-
versity.
*
He spent the latter part of his life in Rome, where
he resided in comparative solitude until his death in 1952. It
is my considered judgment that Santayana’s prose style is
more beautiful than that of any other philosopher since Plato;
and his work, which includes poetry, the novel, and autobi-
ography, can be read as much for its literary charm as for its
__________
*
See also pp. xxxiv-xxxvi.
THE HUMANIST TRADITION
51
intellectual stimulus. His philosophic approach is always so-
phisticated and urbane, treating supernatural religion, for in-
stance, as poetic myth to be enjoyed and understood rather
than as dark superstition to be fought and eradicated. Santa-
yana’s essential tenderness toward the religious tradition has
led one wit aptly to say: “Santayana believes that there is no
God, and that Mary is His mother.”
Santayana’s volumes abound with aphorisms that plainly
have a Humanist intent, as when he tells us that “men be-
came superstitious not b
ecause they had too much imagina-
tion, but because they were not aware that they had any”;
18
that “the fact of having been born is a bad augury for immor-
tality”;
19
and that “the love of God is said to be the root of
Christian charity, but is in reality only its symbol.”
20
As contrasted, however, with the sound approach of his
earlier period and his greatest work,
The Life of Reason
,
Santayana in his later years somewhat weakened his phi-
losophy by adopting an esoteric doctrine of essences, which,
much like the old Platonic ideas, are supposed to subsist in
an eternal realm apart from the regular course of Nature. It is
this feature of Santayana’s thought that led John Dewey to
criticize it as “broken-backed Naturalism.” Santayana some-
times talked of himself as a Naturalist, sometimes as a Hu-
manist, but preferred to think of his system as a species of
Materialism. On political and economic issues he was dis-
tinctly conservative.
Dr. Albert Schweitzer, world famous for his humanitarian-
ism and opposition to nuclear weapons, has sometimes
called himself a Humanist; and his central philosophic prin-
ciple, “Reverence for Life,” has a fine ring. But when we
analyze what he means by this phrase, we discover that for
him “life” includes physical objects and the whole material
universe, so that he turns out to be in a vague way an animist
or a panpsychist. Furthermore, so far as biological species
52
THE PHILOSOPHY OF HUMANISM
are concerned, Dr. Schweitzer’s infinite benevolence extends
to the mosquitoes and microbes that may bring death to hu-
man beings. This is going a bit far for a Humanism primarily
concerned with the welfare of humanity; and it also imposes
psychological guilt on us for killing the worms and germs
that threaten our lives. Naturalistic Humanism, however,
agrees fully with Dr. Schweitzer in favoring kindness to
animals as a principle of human conduct.
Though contemporary Humanism cannot
accept
in toto
any of the Naturalisms, Materialisms, or allied philosophies
discussed above, it must draw primarily, insofar as it de-
pends on past thought, upon these great systems that I have
outlined. Today all philosophy of the first rank must to some
extent be eclectic and acknowledge its heavy debt to earlier
thinkers. To maintain otherwise is to strike an intellectual
pose. Humanism is not interested in novelty as such. Its
question is not whether an idea is old or new, familiar or
daring, but whether it is true and whether it is relevant to the
Humanist outlook.
Even systems such as those of Dualism and Idealism, with
which Humanists so profoundly disagree, have much to
teach us. Almost every philos
ophy contains some important
elements that are sound. And in general it is far more fruitful
to try to understand why certain philosophers went astray
than to neglect or scorn them. Brilliant errors, tenaciously
pursued unto their remotest implications, can be most illumi-
nating and suggestive in the search for truth. That search
follows no royal road, straight and smooth, but meets many
obstacles, makes many false starts, goes off on many attrac-
tive but misleading by-paths. It is a search, too, which is
never-ending, yet which each generation can push forward to
new discoveries and triumphs

Comments